Aristotle
Aristotle is the first philosopher in the
Greek tradition who developed the full technical analysis of final cause. He is
fully aware of that fact and expresses this awareness when he criticizes his
predecessors for failing to understand the crucial value of final cause.for any
serious philosophical explanation of reality.1 This philosophy of
final cause is found mainly in the first book of his Metaphysics and the second
book of Physics. Occasionally he develops the concept of final cause in other
places within the body of his writings. The Aristotelian notion of final cause
deserves a thorough examination on two counts: (a) he is the first one to give
complete metaphysical analysis of final cause, and (b) he influenced in this
respect very deeply the thought of Thomas Aquinas and many other thinkers in
the West.
The Explanation of Change Through
the Employment of the Idea of Act and Potency.
Without a clear knowledge of change (or
motion) there is no understanding of the nature of things since by nature
Aristotle understands that which is the origin of motion and change. “For those
things are natural which by a continuous movement originated from an internal
principle arrive at some completion, but always the tendency is towards the
same end if there is no impediment.” 2 The essential meaning of
“nature” is for Aristotle “…the essence of those things, which have the
principle of movement in themselves, insofar as they are this something.”3
Nature therefore contains the following elements:
(a) it is a principle, a metaphysical beginning or a source, (b) a
principle of movement or change, (c) it is internal, constitutive of the
essence of a being, (d) it is a tendency to a determined end, (e) it is a
tendency towards a state of completion, perfection, actualization.
From the above it is clear that the
analysis of change is the central focus of the Aristotelian Metaphysics and his
Philosophy of Nature. Confronted with the Parmenidean monism of immutable
being, on the one hand, and the obvious, omnipresent and real fact of change on
the other, Aristotle gave a masterly metaphysical analysis of change and
becoming in dynamical terms. Basic Aristotelian insight in this respect remains
true even today. We shall also see that every natural change is intelligible to
him only through the notion of final cause.
In order to solve the problem of change in
general, Aristotle introduces the notion of potency. This notion of “potency”
as correlative to “act” makes change intelligible. The thing which is changing
is in the process of transition from one mode (terminus a quo), to another mode
of being (terminus ad quern). There are two main types of such transition: one,
called accidental, when one and the same being changes and acquires a new state
retaining its proper nature; a second, called substantial, when the transition
is from one nature to another, a different one. One being ceases to exist and a
new one emerges. At this point we are interested in the first type of change.
It occurs in beings composed of potency and act.
Potency as a metaphysical and internal
component is openness, possibility, capacity for a being to move from one
actual mode of existing to another, a new one. It makes newness intelligible.
By newness here we understand the gradual transition to the “terminus ad quem.”
This transition is always a “transition toward,” never something in itself, but
it is a movement of something which itself changes. Something can be in the
movement of change only insofar as it is actually not yet completed, not having
yet what it can have, not completely realized. It cannot at “terminus a quo” be
already what it becomes at “terminus adquem”. The changing movement is
therefore defined by Aristotle as realization of the potential as such.4
A being can exist in three possible modes:
(a) it is not yet moving, (b) it is in the mode of complete realization, full
completion; then it moves no more, (c) it is in the middle mode of
movement-change, in the transition from one mode of being to another, to its
realization.
Change, therefore, is a state of a being which
does not yet fully realize all the potency of “this something” It still is in
the position to acquire new “points of completion.” Each natural change is an
internal going towards its end perfection, or full realization: towards its
final completion. Each natural movement is for the “where-for” or the “good”
for which the movement occurs. Each natural movement has an aim. This, however,
is the Aristotelian definition of final cause 5 proposed, e.g., in
Metaphysics (Bk. XII, Chap. 1): “For final cause is (a) some being for whose
good an action is done, and (b) something at which the action aims.”6
Since we are considering here internal directionality towards final
actualization, this actualization is precisely “that for the sake of which” and „that at which the action aims.” Both
are Aristotelian definitions of final cause.
It remains to show that the internal
finality in natural beings is identical with the form as final cause. Form is
the essence of “that which is coming to be.”7 For it is clear that
the Aristotelian notion of finality is rooted in the analysis of motion-change.
This analysis, as mentioned above, makes the notion of “nature” very clear.
As a matter of fact, for Aristotle both nature and internal final cause are
identical.
No comments:
Post a Comment