The Demiurge, the Ideas and the
Phenomenal World
It would seem that Professor F. M. Cornford
is right in his controversy with Professor A. E. Taylor, when he refuses to
recognize in the Demiurge God with a capital letter and so make of Plato a
monotheist52 Plato believed in the „divinity” of the world as a
whole, and he calls the heavenly bodies, gods. The Demiurge does not create
this world in the sense of giving existence to it. The materials which he
fashions are already (whether logically or ontologically prior) there. He is
never called omnipotent. Quite the contrary, since there is a remnant “errant
cause” left over, so to speak, after his work is done, he only fashions the
cosmos as best he can. But his activity is definitely limited.53 The
material, in some respects, limits the power of the Demiurge. This is the „errant
cause” which Plato acknowledges as present in the world. What seems to be meant
here is that the very structure or the nature of things is limited and thus
does not „give in” to unrestricted manipulation. For our purposes it is
important to realize that the Demiurge is restricted in his activities. Not all
can be indefinitely subdued by him. The material54 „stands against”;
it refuses to submit completely.
The ideas55 as models for the
activity of the Demiurge are never pictured by Plato as dependent on him in any
way. Rather the Demiurge depends on them in the sense that he makes the world
partake of them by ordering the chaos in conformity to the ideas which he
himself must first contemplate. The ideas (Forms) are not said to proceed from
the Demiurge himself. The Form is “…unchanging, indestructible, which neither
receives anything else into itself from elsewhere nor itself enters into
anything else anywhere, invisible and otherwise imperceptible; that in fact
which thinking has for its object.”56
There is no suggestion that the cosmos had
a beginning. It is the fleeting image of the eternal Ideas. The Platonic world
is not material in a strict sense. Its reality consists of the “receptacle”
space, which also is everlasting 57 and which provides a situation
for all things. In space is reflected and situated the sensible reality, which
constantly moves, “coming to be in a certain place and again vanishing out of it.”58 Space is therefore the
“place” and the mirror in which the copies of ideas are fleetingly present. The
world as a whole is endowed with a soul, it is a living organic whole, a
“blessed god” self‑sustaining in its mode of existence. There is no suggestion
that it will ever have an end. The materiality of the world is identical with
extension.
The Demiurge is a necessary agent in the
Platonic scheme. His activity explains why order, design, purpose, reason are
present in this teleologically structured world. I have already explained
the role of the Idea of the Good in the finalistic explanation of the world by
Plato. The idea of the Good is the ultimate cause of this world's orderly
finalistic structure. The Demiurge is a personified element in the sense that
he is the agent through which the Idea of the Good is present and acts in this
world. The activity of the Demiurge is a way of explaining the fact that
finality in this world is ultimately the effect of the idea of the Good
mediated by intelligence. In other words, without the Idea of the Good an
ordered world would not exist, moreover, there would not be any world at all.
The basic difficulty in the Platonic
elaboration of finality in the world is the problem how order and rational
design is introduced into the preexisting chaos. Words like „participation” „being
present to” and similar ones remain somewhat mysterious, and although the
expression “causing” and “causes” occurs in Platonic writings (Republic, Bk.
VI), this happens rather rarely. It is evident from the corpus of Plato's
writings that he struggled with this problem from the earliest dialogues to the
latest. In the Timaeus the Demiurge and his mode of activity, pictured
very vaguely on the model of a human craftsman, remains enigmatic. The presence
of the Demiurge may be an indication that possibly Plato was groping toward the
need for a God as a creator “ex nihilo.” He himself did not go this far.
References
1 Anaxagoras of Clazomenae
was born in the seventieth Olympiad (500-497) and died in the first year of the
eighty-eighth (428). He spent 30 years in Athens and died in Lampsakus. From
among his writings we have only fragments of the First Book preserved by
Simplicius (sixth cent., A.D.). The fragments quoted in this paper are taken
from John Burnet's Early Greek Philosophy (Cleveland: Median Books, 1964).
2 Sir William David Ross,
Aristotle's Metaphysic, revised text
with Introduction and Commentary, 3rd ed. (Oxford, 1953), A3, 984b,
15-19 (hereafter cited as Aristotle, Metaphysics).
3 Hegel, History of
Philosophy, I, 319, quoted in Frederick Charles Copleston, A History of
Philosphy, 4 vols. (Garden City, N. Y.: Image Books, A Division of Doubleday
& Company, Inc., 1964).
4 Copleston, A History of
Philosophy, Part I, I: 87.
5 Metaphysics, A4, 985a,
18-21.
6
Plato,
Phaedo, 97b,8.
7. Burnet, Early Greek
Philosophy, p. 269. The author says: “But in any case, the originality of
Anaxagoras lies far more in the theory of substance than in that of Nous.”
8 Laws, X. This thought is
presented in the first half of the book.
9 Phaedo, 98E.
10 Laws, X, in the greater
part of the book; Phaedrus 254 c-246a; Phaedo, the whole dialogue; Philebus
30e; Timaeus, the whole dialogue.
11 Francis Macdonald Cornford, Plato's Cosmology (New York:
The Liberal Arts Press, 1957), p. 38.
12 Paul Shorey, What Plato
Said (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968), p. 329.
13 This division and plan are
given by F. M. Cornford in his Plato's Cosmology, pp. 9-32. The quotations,
unless otherwise indicated, will be Prof. Burnet's translation used also by
Cornford.
14 Timaeus, 28, 28C.
15 Ibid., 28.
No comments:
Post a Comment